4/10/2022
80
Occasionally Definition Average ratng: 3,0/5 8687 reviews

Definition

Occasionally definition: from time to time Meaning, pronunciation, translations and examples. Definition of occasionally in the Definitions.net dictionary. Meaning of occasionally. Information and translations of occasionally in the most comprehensive dictionary definitions resource on the web.

Also found in: Thesaurus, Wikipedia.

oc·ca·sion·al·ly

(ə-kā′zhə-nə-lē)
adv.
American Heritage® Dictionary of the English Language, Fifth Edition. Copyright © 2016 by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. All rights reserved.

occasionally

(əˈkeɪʒənəlɪ)
adv
Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged, 12th Edition 2014 © HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003, 2006, 2007, 2009, 2011, 2014

oc•ca•sion•al•ly

(əˈkeɪ ʒə nl i)
adv.
[1615–25]
Random House Kernerman Webster's College Dictionary, © 2010 K Dictionaries Ltd. Copyright 2005, 1997, 1991 by Random House, Inc. All rights reserved.
Adv.1.occasionally - now and then or here and there; 'he was arrogant and occasionally callous'; 'open areas are only occasionally interrupted by clumps of trees'; 'they visit New York on occasion'; 'now and again she would take her favorite book from the shelf and read to us'; 'as we drove along, the beautiful scenery now and then attracted his attention'
at times, from time to time, now and again, now and then, on occasion, once in a while
Based on WordNet 3.0, Farlex clipart collection. © 2003-2012 Princeton University, Farlex Inc.
Very occasionally definition

occasionally

adverbsometimes, at times, from time to time, on and off, now and then, irregularly, on occasion, now and again, periodically, once in a while, every so often, at intervals, off and on, (every) now and thenI occasionally go to the cinema with a friend.
often, regularly, constantly, routinely, frequently, continually, continuously, habitually, twenty-four-seven(informal)
Collins Thesaurus of the English Language – Complete and Unabridged 2nd Edition. 2002 © HarperCollins Publishers 1995, 2002

occasionally

adverb1. Once in a while; at times:
betimes, intermittently, periodically, sometimes, sporadically.
2.

Occasionally Definition Synonyms

At rare intervals:
infrequently, little, rarely, seldom, sporadically.
The American Heritage® Roget's Thesaurus. Copyright © 2013, 2014 by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. All rights reserved.
příležitostněobčas
alkalmilagalkalomadtánnagyritkánnéhanapján
때때로
príležitostne
ibland
arada sıradaarasıra

occasionally

[əˈkeɪʒnəlɪ]ADVde vez en cuando, a veces, ocasionalmente (frm), cada cuando (LAm)
he occasionally drinks wine but never beerde vez en cuandoora vecesbebevino pero nunca cerveza
very occasionallymuyde vez en cuando, muy de tarde en tarde
we see each other (only) very occasionallynos vemos (sólo) muyde vez en cuandoormuy de tarde en tarde
Collins Spanish Dictionary - Complete and Unabridged 8th Edition 2005 © William Collins Sons & Co. Ltd. 1971, 1988 © HarperCollins Publishers 1992, 1993, 1996, 1997, 2000, 2003, 2005

occasionally

[əˈkeɪʒənəli]advà l'occasion
very occasionally → occasional table n(British)tablefd'appoint
Collins English/French Electronic Resource. © HarperCollins Publishers 2005

occasionally

advgelegentlich, hin und wieder, zuweilen(geh); very occasionallysehr selten, nicht sehr oft
Collins German Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged 7th Edition 2005. © William Collins Sons & Co. Ltd. 1980 © HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1997, 1999, 2004, 2005, 2007

occasionally

[əˈkeɪʒnlɪ]advogni tanto
very occasionally → molto raramente

Frank Occasionally Definition

Collins Italian Dictionary 1st Edition © HarperCollins Publishers 1995

occasion

(əˈkeiʒən) noun
1. a particular time. I've heard him speak on several occasions. geleentheid; okkasie فُرْصَه момент ocasião příležitost die Gelegenheit lejlighed περίσταση, περίπτωσηocasión juht(um) زمان؛ وقت بخصوص tilanne occasionמקרה, הזדמנות अवसर, प्रसंग prigoda, prilika alkalom kesempatan tækifæri, tilefni occasione 場合 특별한 때 kartas, atvejis, proga gadījums kali gelegenheidanledning, tidspunktokazja ټاكل شوى موده ocasião ocazie случай udalosť priložnost prilika tillfälle โอกาส vesile, münasebet 特定時刻,場合 нагода; випадок وقت dịp 特定时刻,场合
2. a special event. The wedding was a great occasion. geleentheid مُناسَبَه случай ocasião událost der Anlaß begivenhed ειδική περίσταση, γεγονόςocasión, acontecimiento sündmus اتفاق tapahtuma événementמאורה मौका događaj esemény peristiwa viðburður occasione 行事 중요한 행사 įvykis, šventė, renginys notikums; svinības peristiwa evenementanledning, begivenheturoczystość پيښه ocasião eveniment событие udalosť dogodek prilika tilldragelse, händelse โอกาสพิเศษ olay; tören, kutlama 特殊事件 подія موقع dịp đặc biệt 特殊事件
ocˈcasional adjective
happening, done etc now and then. I take an occasional trip to London. nou en dan, af en toe من حين إلى آخَر случаен ocasional příležitostný gelegentlich lejlighedsvis περιστασιακός, σποραδικόςocasional, poco frecuente juhuslik گهگاهی؛ چند وقت یکبار satunnainen qui a lieu de temps en temps מִדֵי פַּעַם समय-समय पर povremen alkalmi sesekali sem gerist endrum og eins occasionale 時折の 임시의 atsitiktinis, retai pasitaikantis, proginis reizēm notiekošs; nejaušs sekali-sekala nu en dan voorkomend som skjer nå og da, leilighetsvis, tilfeldigsporadyczny بعضى وخت infrequente ocazional редкий príležitostný priložnosten povremen sporadisk, tillfällig ซึ่งเป็นครั้งคราว arasıra olan 偶然的 випадковий; такий, що трапляється час від часу کبھي کبھار، وقتاً فوقتاً thỉnh thoảng 偶然的
ocˈcasionally adverb
now and then. I occasionally go to the theatre. nou en dan, soms أحْيانا понякога ocasionalmente občas gelegentlich nu og da σποραδικά, πότε πότε de vez en cuando, a veces vahetevahel گهگاه satunnaisesti de temps en temps מִדי פַּעַם कभी कभी povremeno alkalmilag, néha kadang-kadang öðru hverju occasionalmente 時々 임시로 retkarčiais reizēm; šad un tad sekali-sekala nu en dannå og da, av og tilniekiedy كله كله de vez em quando ocazional иногда príležitostne tu pa tam povremeno då och då, emellanåt บางครั้งบางคราว arasıra 偶然,偶爾,有時候 випадково موقع بہ موقع thỉnh thoảng 偶然,偶尔,有时候
Kernerman English Multilingual Dictionary © 2006-2013 K Dictionaries Ltd.

occasionally

مِن وَقْتٍ لِآخَرٍ příležitostně lejlighedsvisgelegentlichπεριστασιακάde vez en cuando silloin tällöinoccasionnellement povremenosaltuariamente 時折 때때로af en toenå og daod czasu do czasude vez em quando

Occasionally Definition Statistics

случайно ibland บางครั้งบางคราวarada sırada đôi khi偶尔
Multilingual Translator © HarperCollins Publishers 2009
English-Spanish/Spanish-English Medical Dictionary Copyright © 2006 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.

Want to thank TFD for its existence? Tell a friend about us, add a link to this page, or visit the webmaster's page for free fun content.
Link to this page:

Occasionalism is a philosophical theory about causation which says that created substances cannot be efficient causes of events. Instead, all events are taken to be caused directly by God. (A related theory, which has been called 'occasional causation', also denies a link of efficient causation between mundane events, but may differ as to the identity of the true cause that replaces them.[1]) The theory states that the illusion of efficient causation between mundane events arises out of God's causing of one event after another. However, there is no necessary connection between the two: it is not that the first event causes God to cause the second event: rather, God first causes one and then causes the other.

Islamic theological schools[edit]

The doctrine first reached prominence in the Islamic theological schools of Iraq, especially in Basra. The ninth century theologian Abu al-Hasan al-Ash'ari argued that there is no Secondary Causation in the created order. The world is sustained and governed through direct intervention of a divine primary causation. As such the world is in a constant state of recreation by God.

The most famous proponent of the Asharite occasionalist doctrine was Abu Hamid Muhammad ibn Muhammad al-Ghazali, an 11th-century theologian based in Baghdad. In The Incoherence of the Philosophers,[2][page needed] Al-Ghazali launched a philosophical critique against Neoplatonic-influenced early Islamic philosophers such as Al-Farabi and Ibn Sina. In response to the philosophers' claim that the created order is governed by secondary efficient causes (God being, as it were, the Primary and Final Cause in an ontological and logical sense), Ghazali argues that what we observe as regularity in nature based presumably upon some natural law is actually a kind of constant and continual regularity. There is no independent necessitation of change and becoming, other than what God has ordained. To posit an independent causality outside of God's knowledge and action is to deprive Him of true agency, and diminish His attribute of power. In his famous example, when fire and cotton are placed in contact, the cotton is burned not because of the heat of the fire, but through God's direct intervention, a claim which he defended using logic. In the 12th century, this theory was defended and further strengthened by the Islamic theologian Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, using his expertise in the natural sciences of astronomy, cosmology and physics.

Because God is usually seen as rational, rather than arbitrary, His behaviour in normally causing events in the same sequence (i.e., what appears to us to be efficient causation) can be understood as a natural outworking of that principle of reason, which we then describe as the laws of nature. Properly speaking, however, these are not laws of nature but laws by which God chooses to govern His own behaviour (His autonomy, in the strict sense) — in other words, His rational Will. This is not, however, an essential element of an occasionalist account, and occasionalism can include positions where God's behaviour (and thus that of the world) is viewed as ultimately inscrutable, thus maintaining God's essential transcendence. On this understanding, apparent anomalies such as miracles are not really such: they are simply God behaving in a way that appears unusual to us. Given His transcendent freedom, He is not bound even by His own nature. Miracles, as breaks in the rational structure of the universe, can occur, since God's relationship with the world is not mediated by rational principles.

In a 1978 article in Studia Islamica, Lenn Goodman asks the question, 'Did Al-Ghazâlî Deny Causality?'[3] and demonstrates that Ghazali did not deny the existence of observed, 'worldly' causation. According to Goodman's analysis, Ghazali does not claim that there is never any link between observed cause and observed effect: rather, Ghazali argues that there is no necessary link between observed cause and effect.

Dualism[edit]

One of the motivations for the theory is the dualist belief that mind and matter are so utterly different in their essences that one cannot affect the other. Thus, a person's mind cannot be the true cause of his hand's moving, nor can a physical wound be the true cause of mental anguish. In other words, the mental cannot cause the physical and vice versa. Also, occasionalists generally hold that the physical cannot cause the physical either, for no necessary connection can be perceived between physical causes and effects. The will of God is taken to be necessary.

The doctrine is, however, more usually associated with certain seventeenth century philosophers of the Cartesian school. There are hints of an occasionalist viewpoint here and there in Descartes's own writings, but these can mostly be explained away under alternative interpretations.[4] However, many of his later followers quite explicitly committed themselves to an occasionalist position. In one form or another, the doctrine can be found in the writings of: Johannes Clauberg, Claude Clerselier, Gerauld de Cordemoy, Arnold Geulincx, Louis de La Forge, François Lamy, and (most notably), Nicolas Malebranche.

Hume's arguments, Berkeley and Leibniz[edit]

These occasionalists' negative argument, that no necessary connections could be discovered between mundane events, was anticipated by certain arguments of Nicholas of Autrecourt in the fourteenth century, and were later taken up by David Hume in the eighteenth. Hume, however, stopped short when it came to the positive side of the theory, where God was called upon to replace such connections, complaining that 'We are got into fairy land [...] Our line is too short to fathom such immense abysses.'[5] Instead, Hume felt that the only place to find necessary connections was in the subjective associations of ideas within the mind itself. George Berkeley was also inspired by the occasionalists, and he agreed with them that no efficient power could be attributed to bodies. For Berkeley, bodies merely existed as ideas in percipient minds, and all such ideas were, as he put it, 'visibly inactive'.[6] However, Berkeley disagreed with the occasionalists by continuing to endow the created minds themselves with efficient power. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz agreed with the occasionalists that there could be no efficient causation between distinct created substances, but he did not think it followed that there was no efficient power in the created world at all. On the contrary, every simple substance had the power to produce changes in itself. The illusion of transeunt efficient causation, for Leibniz, arose out of the pre-established harmony between the alterations produced immanently within different substances. Leibniz means, that if God did not exist, 'there would be nothing real in the possibilities, not only nothing existent, but also nothing possible.'[7]

Quantum mechanics[edit]

In 1993, Karen Harding's paper 'Causality Then and Now: Al Ghazali and Quantum Theory' described several 'remarkable' similarities between Ghazali's concept of occasionalism and the widely accepted Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. She stated: 'In both cases, and contrary to common sense, objects are viewed as having no inherent properties and no independent existence. In order for an object to exist, it must be brought into being either by God (al-Ghazili) or by an observer (the Copenhagen Interpretation).' She also stated:[8][9][10]

In addition, the world is not entirely predictable. For al Ghazali, God has the ability to make anything happen whenever He chooses. In general, the world functions in a predictable manner, but a miraculous event can occur at any moment. All it takes for a miracle to occur is for God to not follow His ‘custom.’ The quantum world is very similar. Lead balls fall when released because the probability of their behaving in that way is very high. It is, however, very possible that the lead ball may ‘miraculously’ rise rather than fall when released. Although the probability of such an event is very small, such an event is, nonetheless, still possible.

Continuing philosopher Graham Harman's work on Occasionalism in the context of Object Oriented Ontology,[11][12][13] in 2020 Simon Weir proposed an alternate view of the relationship between Quantum theory and Occasionalism, opposed to the Copenhagen Interpretation, where virtual particles act as one of many kinds of mediating sensual objects.[14]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^Steven Nadler, 'The Occasionalism of Louis de la Forge', in Nadler (ed.), Causation in Early Modern Philosophy (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), 57–73; Nadler, 'Descartes and Occasional Causation', British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 2 (1994) 35–54.
  2. ^Griffel, Frank (2010), Al-Ghazali's Philosophical Theology, Oxford University Press.
  3. ^Goodman, Lenn Evan. “Did Al-Ghazâlî Deny Causality?” Studia Islamica, no. 47, 1978, pp. 83–120. JSTOR, JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/1595550.
  4. ^Daniel Garber, Descartes' Metaphysical Physics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 299–305.
  5. ^David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. 7, pt. 1.
  6. ^George Berkeley, A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, sect. 25.
  7. ^Leftow, Brian (1989). 'A Leibnizian Cosmological Argument'. Philosophical Studies. 57 (2): 135–155. doi:10.1007/BF00354595. ISSN0031-8116. JSTOR4320068. S2CID170744902.
  8. ^Harding, Karen (1993-07-01). 'Causality Then and Now: Al Ghazali and Quantum Theory'. American Journal of Islam and Society. 10 (2): 165–177. doi:10.35632/ajis.v10i2.2505. ISSN2690-3741.
  9. ^Harding, Karen (Summer 1993), 'Causality Then and Now: Al Ghazali and Quantum Theory'(PDF), The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences, 10 (2).
  10. ^Harding, Karen (1993). 'Causality Then and Now: Al Ghazali and Quantum Theory'.Cite journal requires journal= (help)
  11. ^Harman, Graham (2010-11-09). 'Time, Space, Essence, and Eidos: A New Theory of Causation'. Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy. 6 (1): 1–17. ISSN1832-9101.
  12. ^Harman, Graham (2010-02-01). 'Asymmetrical Causation: Influence without Recompense'. Parallax. 16 (1): 96–109. doi:10.1080/13534640903478833. ISSN1353-4645. S2CID145281215.
  13. ^Harman, Graham (2016). 'A New Occasionalism?'. Reset Modernity!. ZKM and MIT Press.
  14. ^Weir, Simon (2020-04-21). 'Living and Nonliving Occasionalism'. Open Philosophy. 3 (1): 147–160. doi:10.1515/opphil-2020-0010.

External links[edit]

Occasionally Definition For Kids

  • Occasionalism article in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Retrieved from 'https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Occasionalism&oldid=1002378658'